--------

    Introduction



The lectures "The Tragedy of Tragedy" and "Playwriting" were composed
for a course on drama that Nabokov gave at Stanford during the summer of
1941. We had arrived in America in May of 1940; except for some brief guest
appearances, this was Father's first lecturing engagement at an American
university. The Stanford course also included a discussion of some American
plays, a survey of Soviet theatre, and an analysis of commentary on drama by
several American critics.
The two lectures presented here have been selected to accompany
Nabokov's plays because they embody, in concentrated form, many of his
principal guidelines for writing, reading, and performing plays. The reader
is urged to bear in mind, however, that, later in life, Father might have
expressed certain thoughts differently.
The lectures were partly in typescript and partly in manuscript,
replete with Nabokov's corrections, additions, deletions, occasional slips
of the pen, and references to previous and subsequent installments of the
course. I have limited myself to what editing seemed necessary for the
presentation of the lectures in essay form. If Nabokov had been alive, he
might perhaps have performed more radical surgery. He might also have added
that the gruesome throes of realistic suicide he finds unacceptable onstage
(in "The Tragedy of Tragedy") are now everyday fare on kiddies' TV, while
"adult" entertainment has long since outdone all the goriness of the Grand
Guignol. He might have observed that the aberrations of theatrical method
wherein the illusion of a barrier between stage and audience is shattered --
a phenomenon he considered "freakish" -- are now commonplace: actors wander
and mix; the audience is invited to participate; it is then applauded by the
players in a curious reversal of roles made chic by Soviet performers
ordered to emulate the mise-en-sce´ne of party congresses; and the
term "happening" has already managed to grow obsolescent. He might have
commented that the quest for originality for its own sake has led to
ludicrous excesses and things have taken their helter-skelter course in
random theatre as they have in random music and in random painting.
Yet Nabokov's own plays demonstrate that it is possible to respect the
rules of drama and still be original, just as one can write original poetry
without neglecting the basic requirements of prosody, or play brilliant
tennis, to paraphrase T. S. Eliot, without taking down the net.
There were those who considered Father's professorial persona odd and
vaguely improper. Not only was he unsympathetic to the intrusion of
administrative matters on the academic and to the use of valuable time for
jovial participation in campus life, but he lectured from carefully composed
texts instead of chattily extemporizing. "All of a sudden," say Nabokov, "I
realized that I was totally incapable of public speaking. I decided to write
in advance a good hundred lectures.... Thanks to this method I never
fumbled, and the auditorium received the pure product of my knowledge."1 I
suspect that, since the day when the various Nabokov lectures, resurrected
from notes made more than three decades before, began to appear in print, at
least some of those objectors have realized that Father's single-mindedness
and meticulous preparation had their advantages.
There were even those who resented Nabokov's being allowed to teach at
all, lest the bastions of academic mediocrity be imperiled. Which brings to
mind Roman Jakobson's uneasy quip when Nabokov was being considered for a
permanent position at Harvard: "Are we next to invite an elephant to be
professor of zoology?" If the elephant happens also to be a brilliant
scholar and (as his former Cornell colleague David Daiches put it) a
lecturer whom everyone found "irresistible," why not? Anyway, time has put
things in perspective: those who (attentively) attended Nabokov's lectures
will not soon forget them. Those who missed them regret it but have the
published versions to enjoy. As for Professor Jakobson (and I intend no
malice), I have been racking my brain but cannot, for the life of me, recall
whether or not I took a course of his at some point during my four years at
Harvard. Perhaps what I need is the memory of an elephant.

Dmitri Nabokov.

1 Apostrophes, French television, 1975. (C)Article 3b Trust Under the
Will of Vladimir Nabokov.

--------

    Playwriting



The one and only stage convention that I accept may be formulated in
the following way: the people you see or hear can under no circumstances see
or hear you. This convention is at the same time a unique feature of the
dramatic art: under no circumstances of human life can the most secret
watcher or eavesdropper be absolutely immune to the possibility of being
found out by those he is spying upon, not other people in particular, but
the world as a whole. A closer analogy is the relation between an individual
and outside nature; this, however, leads to a philosophical idea which I
shall refer to at the end of this lecture. A play is an ideal conspiracy,
because, even though it is absolutely exposed to our view, we are as
powerless to influence the course of action as the stage inhabitants are to
see us, while influencing our inner selves with almost superhuman ease. We
have thus the paradox of an invisible world of free spirits (ourselves)
watching uncontrollable but earthbound proceedings, which--a
compensation--are endowed with the power of exactly that spiritual
intervention which we invisible watchers paradoxically lack. Sight and
hearing but no intervention on one side and spiritual intervention but no
sight or hearing on the other are the main features of the beautifully
balanced and perfectly fair division drawn by the line of footlights. It may
be proved further that this convention is a natural rule of the theatre and
that when there is any freakish attempt to break it, then either the
breaking is only a delusion, or the play stops being a play. That is why I
call ridiculous the attempts of the Soviet theatre to have the spectators
join in the play. This is connected with the assumption that the players
themselves are spectators and, indeed, we can easily imagine inexperienced
actors under slapdash management in the dumb parts of attendants just as
engrossed in watching the performance of the great actor in the major part
as we, ordinary spectators, are. But, besides the danger of letting even the
least important actor remain outside the play, there exists one inescapable
law, a law (laid down by that genius of the stage, Stanislavsky) that
invalidates all reasoning deriving from the delusion that the footlights are
not as definite a separation between spectator and player as our main stage
convention implies. Roughly speaking, this law is that, provided he does not
annoy his neighbors, the spectator is perfectly free to do whatever he
pleases, to yawn or laugh, or to arrive late, or to leave his place if he is
bored with the play or has business elsewhere; but the man on the stage,
however inactive and mute he is, is absolutely bound by the conspiracy of
the stage and by its main convention: that is, he may not wander back into
the wings for a drink or a chat, nor may he indulge in any physical
exuberance that would clash with the idea of his part. And, vice-versa, if
we imagine some playwright or manager, brimming over with those collectivist
and mass-loving notions that are a blight in regard to all art, making the
spectators play, too (as a crowd, for instance, reacting to certain doings
or speeches; even going so far as to hand round, for instance, printed words
that the spectators must say aloud, or just leaving these words to our own
discretion; turning the stage loose into the house and having the regular
actors mingle with the audience, etc.), such a method, apart from the
ever-lurking possibility of the play's being wrecked by the local wit or
fatally suffering from the unpreparedness of impromptu actors, is an utter
delusion to boot, because the spectator remains perfectly free to refuse to
participate and may leave the theatre if he does not care for such fooling.
In the case of his being forced to act because the play refers to the
Perfect State and is running in the governmental theatre of a country ruled
by a dictator, the theatre in such case is merely a barbarous ceremony or a
Sunday-school class for the teaching of police regulation--or again, what
goes on in theatre is the same as goes on in the dictator's country, public
life being the constant and universal acting in the dreadful farce composed
by a stage-minded Father of the People.
So far I have dwelt chiefly on the spectator's side of the question:
awareness and nonintervention. But cannot one imagine the players, in
accordance with a dramatist's whim or thoroughly worn-out idea, actually
seeing the public and talking to it from the stage? In other words, I am
trying to find whether there is really no loophole in what I take to be the
essential formula, the essential and only convention of the stage. I
remember, in fact, several plays where this trick has been used, but the
all-important thing is that, when the player stalks up to the footlights and
addresses himself to the audience with a supposed explanation or an ardent
plea, this audience is not the actual audience before him, but an audience
imagined by the playwright, that is, something which is still on the stage,
a theatrical illusion which is the more intensified the more naturally and
casually such an appeal is made. In other words, the line that a character
cannot cross without interrupting the play is this abstract conception that
the author has of an audience; as soon as he sees it as a pink collection of
familiar faces the play stops being a play. To give an instance, my
grandfather, my mother's father, an exceedingly eccentric Russian who got
the idea of having a private theatre in his house and hiring the very
greatest performers of his time to entertain for him and his friends, was on
a friendly footing with most of the actors of the Russian stage and a
regular theatregoer. One night, at one of the St. Petersburg theatres, the
famous Varlamov was impersonating someone having tea on a terrace and
conversing the while with passersby who were invisible to the spectators.
The part bored Varlamov, and that night he brightened it up with certain
harmless inventions of his own. Then at one point he turned in the direction
of my grandfather, whom he espied in the front row, and remarked, quite
naturally, as if speaking to the imaginary passersby:
"By the way, Ivan Vasilich, I'm afraid I shall be unable to have
luncheon with you tomorrow." And just because Varlamov was such a perfect
magician and managed to fit these words so naturally into his scene, it did
not occur to my grandfather that his friend was really and truly canceling
an appointment; in other words, the power of the stage is such, that even
if, as sometimes has happened, an actor in the middle of his performance
falls in a dead faint or, owing to a blunder, a stagehand is trapped among
the characters when the curtain goes up, it will take the spectator much
longer to realize the accident or the mistake than if anything out of the
ordinary happens in the house. Destroy the spell and you kill the play.
My theme being the writing of plays and not the staging of plays, I
shall not develop further what really would lead me into discussing the
psychology of acting. I am merely concerned, let me repeat, with settling
the problem of one convention, so as to fiercely criticize and demolish all
the other minor ones that infect plays. I will prove, I hope, that
continuously yielding to them is slowly but surely killing playwriting as an
art, and that there is no real difficulty in getting rid of them forever,
even if it entails inventing new means, which in their turn will become
traditional conventions with time, to be dismissed again when they stiffen
and hamper and imperil dramatic art. A play limited by my major formula may
be compared to a clock; but when it comes out hobnobbing with the audience,
it becomes a wound-up top, which bumps into something, screeches, rolls on
its side and is dead. Please note, too, that the formula holds not only when
you see a play performed, but also when you read it in a book. And here I
come to a very important point. There exists an old fallacy according to
which some plays are meant to be seen, others to be read. True, there are
two sorts of plays: verb plays and adjective plays, plain plays of action
and florid plays of characterization--but apart from such a classification
being merely a superficial convenience, a fine play of either type is
equally delightful on the stage and at home. The only thing is that a type
of play where poetry, symbolism, description, lengthy monologues tend to
hamper its dramatic action ceases in its extreme form to be a play at all,
becoming a long poem or full-dress speech--so that the question whether it
is better read than seen does not arise, because it is simply not a play.
But, within certain limits, an adjective play is no worse on the stage than
a verb play, though the best plays arc generally a combination of both
action and poetry. For the time being, pending further explanation, we may
assume that a play can be anything it likes, static or tit-for-tatic, round
or fancy-shaped, nimble or stately, provided it is a good play.
We must draw a definite line between the author's gift and the
theatre's contribution. I am speaking only of the former and refer to the
latter insofar as the author has imagined it. It is quite clear that as bad
direction or a bad cast may ruin the best play, the theatre may turn
everything into a couple of hours of fugitive glamour. A nonsense rhyme may
be staged by a director or actor of genius and a mere pun may be turned into
a splendid show owing to the sets of a gifted painter. But all this has
nothing to do with the dramatist's task; it may clarify and bring to life
his suggestions, it can even make a bad play look--and only look--like a
good one; but the merits of the play as disclosed by the printed word are
what they are, not more, not less. In fact, I cannot think of a single fine
drama that is not a pleasure both to see and read, though, to be sure, a
certain part of footlight-pleasure is not the same as the corresponding part
of reading-lamp pleasure, the one being in that part sensual (good show,
fine acting), the other being in the corresponding part purely imaginative
(which is compensated by the fact that any definite incarnation is always a
limitation of possibilities). But the main and most important part of the
pleasure is exactly the same in both cases. It is the delight in harmony,
artistic truth, fascinating surprises, and the deep satisfaction at being
surprised--and, mind you, the surprise is always there even if you have seen
the play and read the book many times. For perfect pleasure the stage must
not be too bookish and the book not too stagy. You will note that
complicated setting is generally described (with very minute details and at
great length) in the pages of the worst plays (Shaw's excepted) and, vice
versa, that very good plays are rather indifferent to the setting. Such
ponderous descriptions of paraphernalia, generally allied with a prefaced
description of the characters and with a whole string of qualifying adverbs
in italics directing every speech in the play, are, more often than not, the
result of an author's feeling that his play does not contain all it is meant
to contain--and so off he goes in a pathetic and long-winded attempt to
strengthen matters by decorative addition. More rarely, such superfluous
ornamentation is dictated by the strong-willed author's desire to have the
play staged and acted exactly as he intended--but even in this case the
method is highly irritating.
We are now ready, as we see the curtain rise, or as we open the book,
to examine the structure of a play itself. But we must be quite clear on one
point. Henceforth, once the initial convention is accepted--spiritual
awareness and physical non-intervention on our side, physical non-awareness
and significant intervention on the part of the play--all others will be
ruled out.
In conclusion, let me repeat in slightly different words--now that I
have defined the general idea--repeat the primary axiom of drama. If, as I
believe it to be, the only acceptable dualism is the unbridgeable division
between ego and non-ego, then we can say that the theatre is a good
illustration of this philosophical fatality. My initial formula referring to
the spectators and the drama onstage may be expressed thus: the first is
aware of the second but has no power over it; the second is unaware of the
first, but has the power of moving it. Broadly speaking, this is very near
to what happens in the mutual relations between myself and the world I see,
and this too is not merely a formula of existence, but also a necessary
convention without which neither I nor the world could exist. I have then
examined certain consequences of the formula convention of the theatre and
found that neither the stage overflowing into the audience nor the audience
dictating its will to the stage can break this convention without destroying
the essential idea of the drama. And here again the concept can be likened,
on a higher level, to the philosophy of existence by saying that in life,
too, any attempt at tampering with the world or any attempt by the world to
tamper with me is extremely risky business even if in both cases the best
intentions are implied. And finally I have spoken of how reading a play and
seeing a play correspond to living one's life and dreaming of one's life, of
how both experiences afford the same pleasure, if in somewhat different
ways.

--------

    The Tragedy of Tragedy



Discussion of the technique of modern tragedy means to me a grim
examination of something which may be termed the tragedy of the art of
tragedy. The bitterness with which I view the plight of playwriting does not
really imply that all is lost and that the contemporary theatre may be
dismissed with that rather primitive gesture--a shrug of the shoulders. But
what I do mean is that unless something is done by somebody, and done soon,
playwriting will cease to be the subject of any discussion dealing with
literary values. The drama will be completely taken over by showmanship,
completely absorbed by that other art, the art of staging and acting, a
great art to be sure which I love ardently but which is as remote from the
writer's essential business as any other art: painting, or music, or
dancing. Thus, a play will be created by the management, the actors, the
stagehands--and a couple of meek scriptwriters whom nobody heeds; it will be
based on collaboration, and collaboration will certainly never produce
anything as permanent as can be the work of one man because however much
talent the collaborators may individually possess the final result will
unavoidably be a compromise between talents, a certain average, a trimming
and clipping, a rational number distilled out of the fusion of irrational
ones. This complete transferring of everything connected with the drama into
hands which, according to my firm belief, are meant to receive the ripe
fruit (the final result of one man's labor), is a rather dismal prospect,
but it may be the logical outcome of the conflict which has been tearing the
drama, and especially tragedy, for several centuries.
First of all let us attempt to define what we mean by "tragedy." As
used in everyday speech, the term is so closely allied to the idea of
destiny as to be almost synonymous with it--at least when the presupposed
destiny is not one that we would be inclined to relish. In this sense,
tragedy without a background of fate is hardly perceptible to the ordinary
observer. If, say, a person goes out and kills another person, of more or
less the same sex, just because he happened to be that day in a more or less
killing mood, there is no tragedy or, more exactly, the murderer in this
case is not a tragic character. He will tell the police that everything went
sort of black and experts will be invited to measure his sanity--that will
be all. But if a perfectly respectable man is slowly but inexorably (and by
the way the "slowly" and the "inexorably" are so used to being together that
the "but" between them ought to be replaced by the wedding ring of an "and")
driven to murder by the creep and crawl of circumstance, or by a
long-repressed passion, or by anything that has long been working at
undermining his will, by things, in short, against which he has been
hopelessly and perhaps nobly struggling--then, whatever his crime, we see in
him a tragic figure. Or again: you happen to meet socially a person of
perfectly normal aspect, good-natured although a little seedy, pleasant
though something of a bore, a trifle foolish, perhaps, but not more so than
anybody else, a character to whom you would never dream of applying the
adjective "tragic"; then you learn that this person several years ago had
been placed by force of circumstance at the head of some great revolution in
a remote, almost legendary country, and that a new force of circumstance had
soon banished him to your part of the world where he lingers on as the mere
ghost of his past glory. Immediately, the very things about the man that had
just seemed to you humdrum (indeed, the very normality of his aspect) now
strike you as the very features of tragedy. King Lear, Nuncle Lear, is even
more tragic when he potters about the place than when he actually kills the
prison guard who was a-hanging his daughter.
So what is the result of our little inquest into the popular meaning of
"tragedy"? The result is that we find the term "tragedy" not only synonymous
with fate, but also synonymous with our knowledge of another man's slow and
inexorable fate. Our next step must be to find what is meant by "fate."
From the two intentionally vague examples that I have selected, one
thing, however, may be clearly deduced. What we learn of another man's fate
is far more than he knows himself. In fact, if he knows himself to be a
tragic figure and acts accordingly, we cease to be interested in him. Our
knowledge of his fate is not objective knowledge. Our imagination breeds
monsters which the subject of our sympathy may never have seen. He may have
been confronted with other terrors, other sleepless nights, other
heartbreaking incidents of which we know nothing. The line of destiny which
ex post facto seems so clear to us may have been in reality a wild scallop
interwoven with other wild scallops of fate or fates. This or that social or
economic background which, if we are Marxist-minded, seems to have played
such an important part in the subject's life may have had nothing to do with
it in this or that particular case, although it does seem to explain
everything so neatly. Consequently, all we possess in regard to our own
judgment of another man's tragic fate is a handful of facts most of which
the man would repudiate; but to this is added what our imagination supplies,
and this imagination of ours is regulated by a sound logic, and this sound
logic of ours is so hypnotized by the conventionally accepted rules of cause
and effect that it will invent a cause and modify an effect rather than have
none at all.
And now observe what has happened. Gossiping around a man's fate has
automatically led us to construct a stage tragedy, partly because we have
seen so many of them at the theatre or at the other place of entertainment,
but mainly because we cling to the same old iron bars of determinism which
have imprisoned the spirit of playwriting for years and years. And this is
where lies the tragedy of tragedy.
Consider the following curious position: on one hand a written tragedy
belongs to creative literature although at the same time it clings to old
rules, to dead traditions which other forms of literature enjoy breaking,
finding in this process perfect liberty, a liberty without which no art can
thrive; and, on the other hand, a written tragedy belongs also to the stage
-- and here too the theatre positively revels in the freedom of fanciful
sets and in the genius of individual acting. The highest achievements in
poetry, prose, painting, showmanship are characterized by the irrational and
illogical, by that spirit of free will that snaps its rainbow fingers in the
face of smug causality. But where is the corresponding development in drama?
What masterpieces can we name except a few dream-tragedies resplendent with
genius, such as King Lear or Hamlet, Gogol's Inspector, and perhaps one or
two Ibsen plays (these last with reservations), what masterpieces can we
name that might be compared to the numberless glories of novels and short
stories and verse produced during these last three or four centuries? What
plays, to put it bluntly, are ever re-read?
The most popular plays of yesterday are on the level of the worst
novels of yesterday. The best plays of today are on the level of magazine
stories and fat best-sellers. And the highest form of the dramatic
art--tragedy--is at its best a clockwork toy made in Greece that little
children wind up on the carpet and then follow on all fours.
I referred to Shakespeare's two greatest plays as dream-tragedies, and
in the same sense I would have called Gogol's Revizor a dream-play, or
Flaubert's Bouvard et Pécuchet a dream-novel. My definition has certainly
nothing to do with that special brand of pretentious "dream-play" which was
at one time popular, and which was really regulated by the most wide-awake
causality, if not by worse things such as Freudianism. I call King Lear or
Hamlet dream-tragedies because dream-logic, or perhaps better say
nightmare-logic, replaces here the elements of dramatic determinism.
Incidentally, I want to stress the point that the way Shakespeare is
produced in all countries is not Shakespeare at all, but a garbled version
flavored with this or that fad which is sometimes amusing as in the Russian
theatre and sometimes nauseating as, for instance, in Piscator's trashy
concoctions. There is something I am very positive about and that is that
Shakespeare must be produced in toto, without a single syllable missing, or
not at all. But from the logical, causal, point of view, that is, from the
point of view of modern producers, both Lear and Hamlet are impossibly bad
plays, and I dare any contemporary popular theatre to stage them strictly
according to the text.
Better scholars than I have discussed the influence of Greek tragedy on
Shakespeare. In my time I have read the Greeks in English translation and
found them very much weaker than Shakespeare though disclosing his influence
here and there. The relays of fire in the Agamemnon of Aeschylus o'erleaping
the plain, flashing across the lake, rambling up the mountainside, or
Iphigenia shedding her crocus-tinctured tunic--these excite me because they
remind me of Shakespeare. But I refuse to be touched by the abstract
passions and vague emotions of those characters, as eyeless and as armless
as that statue which for some reason or other is considered ideally
beautiful; and moreover I do not quite see how a direct contact with our
emotion can be established by Aeschylus when the profoundest scholars
themselves cannot say for sure in what way this or that context points, what
exactly we are to guess here and what there, and then wind up saying that
the removal of the article from this or that word obscures and has in fact
made unintelligible the connection and construction of the sentence. Indeed,
the main drama seems to take place in these minute and copious footnotes.
However, the excitements of inspired grammar are not exactly the emotions
which the theatre can greet, and on the other hand what passes muster as
Greek tragedy on our stage is so far removed from the original, so
influenced by this or that stage version and stage invention, and these in
turn are so influenced by the secondary conventions which the primary ones
of Greek tragedy had engendered, that it is hard to say what we mean when we
praise Aeschylus.
One thing is, however, certain: the idea of logical fate which,
unfortunately, we inherited from the ancients has, ever since, been keeping
the drama in a kind of concentration camp. Now and then a genius would
escape as Shakespeare did more often than not; Ibsen has half-escaped in
Doll's House, while in his Borkman the drama actually leaves the stage and
goes up a winding road, up a remote hill--a curious symbol of that urge
which genius feels to be free from the shackles of convention. But Ibsen has
sinned too: he had spent many years in Scribia, and in this respect the
incredibly absurd results to which the conventions of causality can lead are
well displayed in the Pillars of Society. The plot, as you remember, turns
on the idea of two ships, one good and the other bad. One of them, the
Gypsy, is now in beautiful shape as it lies all ready to sail for America in
the shipyard of which the main character is master. The other ship, the
Indian Girl, is blessed with all the ills that can befall a ship. It is old
and rickety, manned by a wild drunken crew, and it is not repaired before
its return voyage to America--just carelessly patched up by the overseer
(act of sabotage against the new kinds of machinery which lessen the
earnings of workers). The main character's brother is supposed to sail to
America, and the main character has reasons to wish his brother at the
bottom of the sea. Simultaneously, the main character's little son is
secretly preparing to run away to sea. Given these circumstances, the author
was forced by the goblins of cause and effect to subject everything
concerning the ships to the different emotional and physical moves of the
characters with a view to achieving the maximum of effect when,
simultaneously, both brother and son put out to sea--the brother sailing on
the good ship instead of the bad one which, against all rules, knowing it
was rotten, the villain allows to sail, and his adored son heading for the
bad one, so that he will perish through his father's fault. The moves of the
play are exceedingly complicated, and the weather--now stormy, now fair, now
again dirty--is adjusted to these various moves, always in such a manner as
to give the maximum of suspense without bothering about likelihood. When one
follows this "shipyard line" throughout the play, one notices that it forms
a pattern which in a very comical way turns out to be specially, and solely,
adapted to the needs of the author. The weather is forced to resort to the
most eerie dialectical tricks, and, when at the happy ending the ships do
sail (without the boy who has been retrieved just in time, and with the
brother who at the last moment proved to be not worth killing), the weather
suddenly becomes not only fair, but supernaturally fair--and this leads me
to one of the most important points in the dismal technique of modern drama.
The weather, as I say, had been feverishly changing throughout the play
in accordance with the feverish changes of the plot. Now, when at the end of
the play neither of the two ships is meant to sink, the weather turns to
fair, and we know--this is my point--we know that the weather will remain
metaphysically fair after the curtain has gone down, for ever and ever. This
is what I term the positive finality idea. However variable the moves of man
and sky may have been during the four acts, they will retain forever that
particular move which permeates the very last bit of the last act. This
positive-finality idea is a direct consequence of the cause-and-effect idea:
the effect is final because we are limited by the prison regulations we have
adopted. In what we call "real life" every effect is at the same time the
cause of some other effect, so that the classification itself of causality
is merely a matter of standpoint. But, though in "real life" we are not able
to cut away one limb of life from other branching limbs, we do perform this
operation in stage drama, and thus the effect is final, for it is not
supposed to contain any new cause that would explode it somewhere beyond the
play.
A fine specimen of the positive finality motif is the stage suicide.
Here is what happens. The only logical way of leaving the effect of the end
of the play quite pure, i.e. without the faintest possibility of any further
causal transformation beyond the play, is to have the life of the main
character end at the same time as the play. This seems perfect. But is it?
Let us see how the man can be removed permanently. There are three ways:
natural death, murder, and suicide. Now, natural death is ruled out because,
however patiently prepared, however many heart attacks the patient endures
in the exposition, it is almost impossible for a determinist playwright to
convince a determinist audience that he has not been helping the hand of
God; the audience will inevitably regard such a natural death as an evasion,
an accident, a weak unconvincing end, especially as it must happen rather
suddenly, so as not to interfere with the last act by a needless display of
agony. I presuppose naturally that the patient has been struggling with
fate, that he has sinned, etc. I certainly do not mean that natural death is
always unconvincing: it is only the cause-and-effect idea that makes natural
death occurring at the right moment look a little too smart. So this first
method is excluded.
The second one is murder. Now, murder is all very well at the beginning
of a play. It is a very uncomfortable thing to have at its close. The man
who has sinned and struggled, etc., is doubtlessly removed. But his murderer
remains, and even if we may be plausibly sure that society will pardon him,
we are left with the uncomfortable sensation that we do not exactly know how
he will feel in the long years following the final curtain; and whether the
fact of his having murdered a man, however necessary it might have been,
will not influence somehow all his future life, for instance his
relationship with the still unborn but imaginable children. In other words,
the given effect breeds a vague but quite disagreeable little cause which
keeps moving like a worm in a raspberry, worrying us after the curtain has
gone down. In examining this method I assume, of course, that the murder is
a direct consequence of a previous conflict and in this sense it is easier
to bring about than natural death. But, as I have explained, the murderer
remains, and the effect is not final.
So we come to the third method, suicide. It can be used either
indirectly, with the murderer first killing the hero and then himself, so as
to remove all traces of what is really the author's crime, or it can be used
directly with the main character taking his own life. This again is easier
to pull off than natural death, as it is rather plausible for a man, after a
hopeless struggle with hopeless circumstances, to take his fate into his
hands. No wonder, then, that of the three methods suicide is your
determinist's favorite. But here a new and awful difficulty arises. Though a
murder can be, à la rigueur, staged directly before our eyes, it is
extraordinarily difficult to stage a good suicide. It was feasible in the
old days, when such symbolic instruments as daggers and bodkins were used,
but nowadays we can't very well show a man cutting his throat with a
Gillette blade. Where poison is employed the agonies of the suicidee can be
too horrible to watch, and are sometimes too lengthy, while the implication
that the poison was so strong that the man just fell dead is somehow neither
fair nor plausible. Generally speaking the best way out is the pistol shot,
but it is impossible to show the actual thing--because, again, if treated in
a plausible manner, it is apt to be too messy for the stage. Moreover, any
suicide on the stage diverts the attention of the audience from the moral
point or from the plot itself, exciting in us the pardonable interest with
which we watch how an actor will proceed to kill himself plausibly and
politely with the maximum of thoroughness and the minimum of bloodshed.
Showmanship can certainly find many practical methods while actually leaving
the actor on the stage, but, as I say, the more elaborate the thing is, the
more our minds wander away from the inner spirit to the outer body of the
dying actor--always assuming that it is an ordinary cause-and-effect play.
We are left thus with only one possibility: the backstage pistol-shot
suicide
. And you will remember that, in stage directions, the author will
generally describe this as a "muffled shot." Not a good loud bang, but "a
muffled shot," so that sometimes there is an element of doubt among the
characters on the stage regarding that sound, though the audience knows
exactly what that sound was. And now comes a new and perfectly awful
difficulty. Statistics--and statistics are the only regular income of your
determinist, just as there are people who make a regular income out of
careful gambling--show that, in real life, out of ten attempts at suicide by
pistol shot, as many as three are abortive, leaving the subject alive; five
result in a long agony; and only two bring on instant death. Thus, even if
the characters do understand what happens, a mere muffled shot is
insufficient to convince us that the man is really dead. The usual method,
then, after the muffled shot has cooed its message, is to have a character
investigate and then come back with the information that the man is dead.
Now, except in the rare case when the investigator is a physician, the mere
sentence "He is dead," or perhaps something "deeper" like, for instance, "He
has paid his debt," is hardly convincing coming from a person who, it is
assumed, is neither sufficiently learned nor sufficiently careless to wave
aside any possibility, however vague, of bringing the victim back to life.
If, on the other hand, the investigator comes back shrieking, "Jack has shot
himself! Call a doctor at once!" and the final curtain goes down, we are
left wondering whether, in our times of patchable hearts, a good physician
might not save the mangled party. Indeed, the effect that is fondly supposed
to be final may, beyond the play, start a young doctor of genius upon some
stupendous career of life-saving. So, shall we wait for the doctor and see
what he says and then ring down the curtain? Impossible--there is no time
for further suspense; the man, whoever he is, has paid his debt and the play
is over. The right way, then, is to add, after "debt," "It is too late to
call a doctor"; that is, we introduce the word "doctor" as a kind of
symbolic or masonic sign--not meaning, say, that we (the messenger) are
sufficiently learned and sufficiently unsentimental to know that no doctor
will help, but conveying to the audience by a conventional sign, by this
rapid "doctor" sound, something that stresses the positive finality of the
effect. But actually there is no way of making the suicide quite, quite
final, unless, as I said, the herald himself be a doctor. So we come to the
very curious conclusion that a really ironclad tragedy, with no possible
chink in cause or effect--that is, the ideal play that textbooks teach
people to write and theatrical managers clamor for--that this masterpiece,
whatever its plot or background, 1) must end in suicide, 2) must contain one
character at least
who is a doctor, 3) that this doctor must be a good
doctor
and, 4) that it is he who must find the body. In other words, from
the mere fact of tragedy's being what it is we have deduced an actual play.
And this is the tragedy of tragedy.
In speaking of this technique, I have begun at the end of a modern
tragedy to show what it must aspire to if it wants to be quite, quite
consistent. Actually, the plays you may remember do not conform to such
strict canons, and thus are not only bad in themselves, but do not even
trouble to render plausible the bad rules they follow. For, numerous other
conventions are unavoidably bred by the causal convention. We may hastily
examine some of these.
A more sophisticated form of the French "dusting the furniture"
exposition is when, instead of the valet and the maid discovered onstage, we
have two visitors arriving on the stage as the curtain is going up, speaking
of what brought them, and of the people in the house. It is a pathetic
attempt to comply with the request of critics and teachers who demand that
the exposition coincide with action, and actually the entrance of two
visitors is action. But why on earth should two people who arrived on the
same train and who had ample time to discuss everything during the journey,
why must they struggle to keep silent till the minute of arrival, whereupon
they start talking of their hosts in the wrongest place imaginable--the
parlor of the house where they are guests? Why? Because the author must have
them explode right here with a time-bomb exposition.
The next trick, to take the most obvious ones, is the promise of
somebody's arrival. So-and-so is expected. We know that so-and-so will
unavoidably come. He or she will come very soon. In fact he or she comes a
minute after it has been said that the arrival will occur perhaps after
dinner, perhaps tomorrow morning (which is meant to divert the audience's
attention from the rapidity of the apparition: "Oh, I took an earlier train"
is the usual explanation). If, when promising the audience a visitor, the
speaker remarks that by the by so-and-so is coming--this by the by is a
pathetic means of concealing the fact that so-and-so will play a most
important, if not the most important, part in the play. Indeed, more often
than not the "by and by" brings in the so-called fertilizing character.
These promises, being links in the iron chain of tragic causation, are
inevitably kept. The so-called scène à faire, the obligatory scene, is not,
as most critics seem to think, one scene in the play--it is really every
next scene in the play, no matter how ingenious the author may be in the way
of surprises, or rather just because he is expected to surprise. A cousin
from Australia is mentioned; somehow or other the characters expect him to
be a grumpy old bachelor; now, the audience is not particularly eager to
meet a grumpy old bachelor; but the cousin from Australia turns out to be
the bachelor's fascinating young niece. The arrival is an obligatory scene
because any intelligent audience had vaguely expected the author to make
some amends for promising a bore. This example refers certainly more to
comedy than to tragedy, but analogous methods are employed in the most
serious plays: for example, in Soviet tragedies where more often than not
the expected commissar turns out to be a slip of a girl--and then this slip
of a girl turns out to be an expert with a revolver when another character
turns out to be a bourgeois Don Juan in disguise.
Among modern tragedies there is one that ought to be studied
particularly closely by anyone wishing to find all the disastrous results of
cause and effect, neatly grouped together in one play. This is O'Neill's
Mourning Becomes Electra. Just as the weather changed according to human
moods and moves in Ibsen's play, here, in Mourning Becomes Electra, we
observe the curious phenomenon of a young woman who is flat-chested in the
first act, becomes a full-bosomed beautiful creature after a trip to the